This presentation uses javascript. Please enable it or switch to a browser that uses it.

Varieties of De Morgan monoids

PhD Defense July 2020

J. J. Wannenburg

  1. University of Pretoria, South Africa, funded by DST-NRF Centre of Excellence in Mathematical and Statistical Sciences (CoE-MaSS)

Supervisor: J. G. Raftery; Co-supervisor: T. Moraschini

Opinions expressed and conclusions arrived at are those of the author and are not necessarily to be attributed to the CoE-MaSS.

De Morgan monoids

A De Morgan monoid \(\mathbf{A} = \langle A; \vee, \wedge, \cdot, \neg, e \rangle\) comprises

\[x \cdot y \leqslant z \text{ if and only if } x \cdot \neg z \leqslant \neg y.\]

Defining \(y \to z = \neg(y \cdot \neg z)\) and \(f=\neg e\),

we obtain the law of residuation: \[ x \cdot y \leqslant z \text{ iff } x \leqslant y \to z, \] and \(\neg x = x \to f\).

The class of all De Morgan monoids, \(\mathsf{DMM}\), is a variety.

\(\mathbf{R^t}\)

The relevance logic \(\mathbf{R^t}\) can be characterized as follows, \[ \vdash_{\mathbf{R^t}} \alpha \;(\alpha \text{ is a theorem of } \mathbf{R^t}) \;\text{ iff }\; \mathsf{DMM} \models e \leqslant \alpha. \;(\text{Dunn 1966})\]

More generally, in the deducibility relation of the usual formal system for \(\mathbf{R^t}\), we have \(\gamma_1 , \dots, \gamma_n \vdash_{\mathbf{R^t}} \alpha\) iff \[ \mathsf{DMM} \models \overbrace{(e \leqslant \gamma_1\, \& \dots \&\, e \leqslant \gamma_n) \implies e \leqslant \alpha}^{\text{a quasi-equation}}. \]

There is a lattice anti-isomorphism from the subquasivarieties of \(\mathsf{DMM}\) to the extensions of \(\mathbf{R^t}\), taking subvarieties onto axiomatic extensions.

















Some history

Relevance logic began in protest at ‘paradoxes’ of material implication, e.g., the weakening axiom \(p \to (q \to p)\).

It has multiple interpretations, however, and now fits under the ideology-free umbrella of substructural logics.

Relative to these, \(\mathbf{R^t}\) adds \(\wedge\), \(\vee\) distributivity and the contraction axiom \((p \to (p\to q))\to(p\to q)\).

Urquhart (1984)
\(\mathbf{R^t}\) is undecidable.

Algebraic effects

Contraction amounts to the square-increasing law \(x\leqslant x^2\) of \(\mathsf{DMM}\). Its effects include:

On the other hand, \(\wedge,\vee\) distributivity gives:

Special features of De Morgan monoids:

Fact
In a De Morgan monoid, the demand \(f\leqslant e\) is equivalent to idempotence of the whole algebra: \(x^2=x\) (for all \(x\)).

So, non-idempotent algebras lack idempotent subalgebras.

Sugihara monoids

Idempotent De Morgan monoids (a.k.a. Sugihara monoids) form a locally finite variety \[\mathsf{SM} = \mathbb{V}(\mathbf{S}^*)\] \[\;\;(:= \text{ smallest variety containing } \mathbf{S}^*),\] where \(\mathbf{S}^*\) is the natural chain of nonzero integers (with \(-\) as \(\neg\)), \[ x \cdot y = \begin{cases} \text{whichever of }x,y\text{ has} \\ \quad\text{ a greater absolute value} \\ \text{or } x \wedge y \text{ if } \lvert x \rvert = \lvert y \rvert. \end{cases}\]

Here, \(e = 1\), so \(f = -1\).




\(\mathbf{S}^*\) has a homomorphic image \(\mathbf{S}\) in which just \(1\) and \(-1\) are identified.

Up to isomorphism, \(\mathbf{S}\) could be defined like \(\mathbf{S}^*\) on the set of all integers.

Then \(\mathbf{S} \models f = e \,(= 0)\).

Algebras with \(f = e\) are called odd.





The \(n\)-element (unique) convex subalgebra of \(\mathbf{S}^*\) or \(\mathbf{S}\) is denoted \(\mathbf{S}_n\).

E.g. \(\mathbf{S}_2\) is the Boolean algebra \(-1<1\);

\(\mathbf{S}_3\) is \(-1 < 0 < 1\);

\(\mathbf{S}_4\) is \(-2<-1<1<2\);

\(\mathbf{S}_5\) is \(-2 < -1 < 0 < 1 < 2\), etc.

These are exactly the finitely generated irreducible Sugihara monoids (Dunn, 1970s), so \(\mathsf{SM}\) is semilinear (i.e., Sugihara monoids are subdirect products of chains).

For \(\mathbf{A} \in \mathsf{DMM}\), the variety \(\mathbb{V}(\mathbf{A})\) contains no nontrivial Sugihara monoid iff \(\mathbf{A}\) satisfies \(x \leqslant f^2\). Then call \(\mathbf{A}\) ‘anti-idempotent’.

Beyond Sugihara monoids, the structure of De Morgan monoids is not fully understood, but here’s a new structure theorem:

Thm

Let \(\mathbf{A}\) be an irreducible De Morgan monoid. Then, either

  1. \(\mathbf{A}\) is a totally ordered Sugihara monoid, with \(f<e\), or
  2. \(\mathbf{A}\) is the union of an anti-idempotent interval subalgebra \([\neg(f^2),f^2] := \{x\in A : \neg(f^2)\leqslant x\leqslant f^2\}\) and two chains of idempotent elements, \((\neg(f^2)]\) and \([f^2)\).

The algebra \(\mathbf{A}/\Theta(\neg(f^2),e)\) is an odd Sugihara monoid, and the \(\Theta(\neg(f^2),e)\)-classes other than \([\neg(f^2),f^2]\) are singletons.

Atoms

The simple \(0\)-generated De Morgan monoids are just \(\mathbf{2} \,(=\mathbf{S}_2), \mathbf{C}_4\) and \(\mathbf{D}_4\) below (Slaney, 1980s).

Thm

A variety of De Morgan monoids consists of Sugihara monoids iff it omits \(\mathbf{C}_4\) and \(\mathbf{D}_4\).

Cor

The minimal varieties of De Morgan monoids are just \(\mathbb{V}(\mathbf{2})\,(=\{\text{Boolean algebras}\})\), \(\mathbb{V}(\mathbf{S}_3)\), \(\mathbb{V}(\mathbf{C}_4)\) and \(\mathbb{V}(\mathbf{D}_4)\).

















On general grounds, \(\mathbb{V}(\mathbf{2})\), \(\mathbb{V}(\mathbf{S_3})\), \(\mathbb{V}(\mathbf{C}_4)\) and \(\mathbb{V}(\mathbf{D}_4)\) are also minimal as quasivarieties, but they are not the only ones.

Thm

There are just 68 minimal quasivarieties of De Morgan monoids.

Covers of \(\mathbb{V}(\mathbf{2})\) and \(\mathbb{V}(\mathbf{S}_3)\)

Thm

Covers of \(\mathbb{V}(\mathbf{D}_4)\)

Thm

Every join-irreducible cover of \(\mathbb{V}(\mathbf{D}_4)\) has the form \(\mathbb{V}(\mathbf{A})\) for some simple 1-generated De Morgan monoid \(\mathbf{A}\), where \(\mathbf{D}_4\) is a proper subalgebra of \(\mathbf{A}\).

  • For every prime \(p\), the algebra \(\mathbf{B}_p\) generates a cover of \(\mathbb{V}(\mathbf{D}_4)\).
  • There are infinitely many finitely generated covers of \(\mathbb{V}(\mathbf{D}_4)\).

Not all covers of \(\mathbb{V}(\mathbf{D}_4)\) are finitely generated.

  • E.g., \(\mathbf{B}_\infty\) is the subalgebra generated by \(a\) in an ultraproduct of the algebras \(\mathbf{B}_p\).
  • The variety \(\mathbb{V}(\mathbf{B}_\infty)\) covers \(\mathbb{V}(\mathbf{D}_4)\) but it is not generated by its finite members.

Covers of \(\mathbb{V}(\mathbf{C}_4)\)

Distinctive, as \(\mathbf{C}_4\) has diverse homomorphic pre-images:

Thm (Slaney 1989)

If \(h : \mathbf{A} \to \mathbf{B}\) is a homomorphism from an irreducible De Morgan monoid into a non-trivial 0-generated De Morgan monoid, then \(h\) is an isomorphism or \(\mathbf{B} \cong \mathbf{C}_4\).

Thm

If \(\mathsf{K}\) is a join-irreducible cover of \(\mathbb{V}(\mathbf{C}_4)\), then exactly one of the following holds:

  1. \(\mathsf{K} = \mathbb{V}(\mathbf{A})\) for some simple 1-generated De Morgan monoid \(\mathbf{A}\), such that \(\mathbf{C}_4\) is a proper subalgebra of \(\mathbf{A}\).
  2. \(\mathsf{K} = \mathbb{V}(\mathbf{A})\) for some (finite) non-trivial 0-generated irreducible De Morgan monoid \(\mathbf{A} \in \mathsf{U} \setminus \mathsf{M}\).
  3. \(\mathsf{K} \subseteq \mathsf{M}\).

Condition 1

  1. \(\mathsf{K} = \mathbb{V}(\mathbf{A})\) for some simple 1-generated De Morgan monoid \(\mathbf{A}\), such that \(\mathbf{C}_4\) is a proper subalgebra of \(\mathbf{A}\).
  • For each prime \(p\), the algebra \(\mathbf{A}_p\) generates a cover of \(\mathbb{V}(\mathbf{C}_4)\).
  • Thus there are infinitely many finitely generated covers of \(\mathbb{V}(\mathbf{C}_4)\) that satisfy condition 1.
  • Some covers of \(\mathbb{V}(\mathbf{C}_4)\) are not finitely generated,
  • for example \(\mathbf{A_\infty}\) generates a cover of \(\mathbb{V}(\mathbf{C}_4)\).

Condition 2

  1. \(\mathsf{K} = \mathbb{V}(\mathbf{A})\) for some (finite) non-trivial 0-generated irreducible De Morgan monoid \(\mathbf{A} \in \mathsf{U} \setminus \mathsf{M}\).

Slaney (1989) characterized all the \(0\)-generated irreducible De Morgan monoids. They are all finite, and apart from the simple and non-trivial ones, they are:

















Condition 3

  1. \(\mathsf{K} \subseteq \mathsf{M}\).

Every irreducible algebra in \(\mathsf{M}\) arises by a construction of Slaney (1993) from a Dunn monoid \(\mathbf{B}\) (essentially a De Morgan monoid without an involution \(\neg\)), i.e.,

a square-increasing distributive lattice-ordered commutative monoid \(\langle B; \vee,\wedge,\cdot,\to,e\rangle\) satisfying the law of residuation \[ x \leqslant y \to z \text{ iff } x \cdot y \leqslant z.\]

Let’s call this construction skew reflection.

Skew reflection

Declare that \(a < b'\) for certain \(a,b \in B\) in such a way that \(\langle B \cup B' \cup \{\bot,\top\}; \leqslant \rangle\) is a distributive lattice, \(e < e'\) and for all \(a,b \in B\), \[a < b' \text{ iff } e < (a \cdot b)'.\] Then there is a unique way of turning the structure into a De Morgan monoid \[S^<(\mathbf{B}) = \langle B \cup B' \cup \{ \bot ,\top \}; \vee, \wedge, \cdot, \neg, e \rangle \in \mathsf{M},\] of which \(\mathbf{B}\) is a subreduct, where \(\neg\) extends \('\).

In particular, if we specify that \(a < b'\) for all \(a,b \in B\), then we get the reflection construction—an older idea, see Meyer (1973).

In this case we write \(R(\mathbf{B})\) for \(S^<(\mathbf{B})\).

Covers of \(\mathbb{V}(\mathbf{C}_4)\) within \(\mathsf{M}\)

Thm

Let \(\mathsf{K}\) be a cover of \(\mathbb{V}(\mathbf{C}_4)\) within \(\mathsf{M}\). Then \(\mathsf{K} = \mathbb{V}(\mathbf{A})\) for some finite skew reflection \(\mathbf{A}\) of an irreducible Dunn monoid \(\mathbf{B}\), where \(\bot\) is meet-irreducible in \(\mathbf{A}\), and \(\mathbf{A}\) is generated by the greatest strict lower bound \(c\) of \(e\) in \(\mathbf{B}\).

There are just six such algebras:

















Singly generated varieties

Consider a logic \(\,\vdash\), algebraized by a variety \(\mathsf{K}\) of algebras.

It may happen (as in classical prop. logic) that the derivable inference rules of \(\,\vdash\) are determined by a single set of ‘truth tables’, i.e., by the operation tables of a single member of \(\mathsf{K}\).

This happens just in case \(\mathsf{K}=\mathbb{Q}(\mathbf{A})\) for some \(\mathbf{A}\in\mathsf{K}\).

Thm [essentially Maltsev 1966; Łoś & Suszko 1958]

The following conditions on a variety \(\mathsf{K}\) are equivalent.

  1. \(\mathsf{K}=\mathbb{Q}(\mathbf{A})\) for some \(\mathbf{A}\in\mathsf{K}\) (i.e., \(\mathsf{K}\) is ‘singly generated’).
  2. \(\mathsf{K}\) has the joint embedding property (JEP), i.e., any two non-trivial members of \(\mathsf{K}\) both embed into some third member.
  3. (a robust ‘relevance principle’): For any finite set \(\Gamma\cup\Delta\cup\{\alpha\thickapprox\beta\}\) of equations, where \(\Gamma\) is satisfiable in a nontrivial member of \(\mathsf{K}\) and involves different variables from \(\Delta\cup\{\alpha\thickapprox\beta\}\), if \(\mathsf{K}\models (\&(\Gamma\cup\Delta))\Rightarrow\alpha\thickapprox\beta\), then \(\mathsf{K}\models (\&\Delta)\Rightarrow\alpha\thickapprox\beta\).

Known variants of the JEP:

A variety \(\mathsf{K}\) is

  1. structurally complete (SC) if \(\mathsf{K}=\mathbb{Q}(\mathbf{F}_{\mathsf{K}}(\aleph_0))\);
  2. passively structurally complete (PSC) if any two nontrivial members of \(\mathsf{K}\) satisfy the same existential positive sentences \(\exists x_1\,\dots\,\exists x_n\,\Phi\)

(\(\Phi\) a disjunction of conjunctions of equations).

Note
PSC is hereditary. Also, SC implies PSC.

Thm

Every PSC variety has the JEP (hereditarily).

\[\text{SC} \Rightarrow \text{PSC} \Rightarrow \text{JEP}\quad(\not\Leftarrow)\]

Thm

A variety \(\mathsf{K}\) of De Morgan monoids has the JEP iff one of the following (mutually exclusive) conditions holds.

  1. \(\mathsf{K}\) is PSC (classified further in the next theorem).
  2. \(\mathsf{K}=\mathbb{V}(\mathbf{A})\) for a simple De Morgan monoid \(\mathbf{A}\) that has \(\mathbf{D}_{4}\) as a proper subalgebra.
  3. \(\mathsf{K}=\mathbb{Q}(\mathbf{A})\) for a De Morgan monoid \(\mathbf{A}\) that has a simple subalgebra \(\mathbf{B}\), where \(\mathbf{C}_{4}\) is a proper subalgebra of \(\mathbf{B}\).

Thm

A variety \(\mathsf{K}\) of De Morgan monoids is PSC iff one of the following (mutually exclusive) conditions holds.

  1. \(\mathsf{K}\) is \(\mathbb{V}(\mathbf{2})\) or \(\mathbb{V}(\mathbf{D}_{4})\).
  2. \(\mathsf{K}\) consists of odd Sugihara monoids, i.e., it is one of \[ \mathbb{V}(\mathbf{S}_1) \subsetneq \mathbb{V}(\mathbf{S}_3) \subsetneq \mathbb{V}(\mathbf{S}_5) \subsetneq \dots \subsetneq \mathbb{V}(\mathbf{S})\]
  3. \(\mathsf{K}\) is a nontrivial subvariety of \(\mathsf{M}\).

In (1) and (2), \(\mathsf{K}\) is structurally complete (SC).

So, except for (1),(2), all SC subvarieties of \(\mathsf{DMM}\) lie within \(\mathsf{M}\).

In contrast with (1),(2), we can prove:

Thm

\(\mathsf{M}\) has \(2^{\aleph_0}\) (locally finite) subvarieties \(\mathsf{K}\) that are structurally incomplete—i.e., \(\mathsf{K}=\mathbb{V}(\mathsf{L})\) for some proper subquasivariety \(\mathsf{L}\) of \(\mathsf{K}\); in particular, \(\mathbb{Q}(\mathbf{F}_{\mathsf{K}}(\aleph_0))\subsetneq\mathsf{K}\).

(Where \(\mathsf{K}\) algebraizes a logic \(\,\vdash\), this means that \(\,\vdash\) possesses proper extensions having no new theorems.)

Thm

In the join \(\mathsf{J}\) of the six covers of \(\mathbb{V}(\mathbf{C}_4)\) within \(\mathsf{M}\), every subquasivariety is a variety, i.e., every subvariety of \(\mathsf{J}\) is structurally complete.

Epimorphisms

In a variety \(\mathsf{K}\) of algebras, a homomorphism \(h\colon\mathbf{A}\rightarrow\mathbf{B}\) is called a

(\(\mathsf{K}\)-)epimorphism provided that

\(f \circ h= g\circ h\) implies \(f=g\) (for all \(\mathsf{K}\)-morphisms \(f,g \colon\mathbf{B}\rightarrow\mathbf{C}\)).




Note

  1. Surjective homomorphisms are epimorphisms.
  2. We say that \(\mathsf{K}\) has the ES property if all \(\mathsf{K}\)-epimorphisms are surjective.
  3. \(h\) is an epimorphism iff the inclusion \(h[\mathbf{A}]\rightarrow \mathbf{B}\) is.
  4. \(\mathsf{K}\) has the ES property iff no \(\mathbf{B}\in \mathsf{K}\) has a proper (\(\mathsf{K}\)-)epic subalgebra \(\mathbf{D}\), i.e., one such that every \(\mathsf{K}\)-morphism \(f\colon\mathbf{B}\rightarrow\mathbf{C}\) is determined by \(f|_{\mathbf{D}}\).

Beth property

If a variety \(\mathsf{K}\) algebraizes a logic \(\,\vdash\), then

\(\mathsf{K}\) has the ES property iff \(\,\vdash\) has the infinite (deductive) Beth (definability) property, i.e.,

whenever a set \(Z\) of variables is defined implicitly in terms of a disjoint set \(X\) of variables by means of some set \(\Gamma\) of formal assertions about \(X \cup Z\), then \(\Gamma\) also defines \(Z\) explicitly in terms of \(X\).

‘implicitly defined’ \(\equiv\) ‘uniquely determined or non-existent’, e.g.,

Question
Which varieties of De Morgan monoids have surjective epimorphisms?

A Brouwerian algebra \(\mathbf{B}=\langle B; \wedge, \vee, \to, e\rangle\) is a distributive lattice with a binary \(\to\) satisfying \[ x \leqslant y \to z \;\text{ iff }\; x \wedge y \leqslant z.\] I.e., it’s a Dunn monoid in which \(x \cdot y = x \wedge y\)

(so \(e\) is its top element).

In any De Morgan monoid \(\mathbf{A}\), if \(x,y \leqslant e\) then \(x \cdot y = x \wedge y\).

The negative cone \(A^- := \{ a \in A : a \leqslant e\}\) of \(\mathbf{A}\) can be turned into a Brouwerian algebra \(\mathbf{A}^- = \langle A^-; \wedge, \vee, \to^-, e \rangle\), by restricting the operations \(\wedge, \vee\) to \(A^-\) and defining \[ a \to^- b = (a \to b) \wedge e, \text{ for } a,b \in A^-.\]

A prime filter of a Brouwerian algebra \(\mathbf{B}\) is a lattice-filter \(F\) such that \(B \setminus F\) is closed under \(\vee\).

The depth of \(F\) is the greatest \(n \in \mathbb{N}\) (if it exists) such that there’s a chain of prime filters in \(\mathbf{B}\) of the form \(F = F_0 \subsetneq F_1 \subsetneq \dots \subsetneq F_n = B\).

If no greatest such \(n\) exists, we say \(F\) has depth \(\infty\).

Define \(\text{depth}(\mathbf{B}) = \sup\{\text{depth}(F): F \text{ a prime filter of } \mathbf{B}\}.\)

If \(\mathbf{A}\) is a De Morgan monoid and \(\mathsf{K}\) a variety of De Morgan monoids, we define \[\text{depth}(\mathbf{A}) = \text{depth}(\mathbf{A}^-);\quad \text{depth}(\mathsf{K}) = \sup\{\text{depth}(\mathbf{A}) : \mathbf{A} \in \mathsf{K}\}.\]

Thm

Let \(\mathsf{K}\) be a variety of De Morgan monoids such that

  1. Each irreducible member of \(\mathsf{K}\) is generated by its negative cone;
  2. \(\mathsf{K}\) has finite depth.

Then \(\mathsf{K}\) has surjective epimorphisms (ES).

Thm

Let \(\mathsf{C}\) be the class of all semilinear De Morgan monoids that are generated by their negative cones. Then

  1. \(\mathsf{C}\) is locally finite variety with ES (despite infinite depth);
  2. every subvariety of \(\mathsf{C}\) has ES.

Thm

There are \(2^{\aleph_0}\) locally finite varieties of De Morgan monoids without the ES property.

thank you

Implicit definitions

Let \(\mathsf{K}\) be a variety of algebras. The following are equivalent:

Let \(\,\vdash\) be an algebraizable logic.

Consider two disjoint sets \(X\) and \(Z\) of variables, with \(X \neq \emptyset\), and a set \(\Gamma\) of formulas over \(X \cup Z\). We say that \(Z\) is defined implicitly in terms of \(X\) by means of \(\Gamma\) in \(\vdash\) if \[ \Gamma \cup \sigma[\Gamma] \vdash z \leftrightarrow \sigma(z) \] for every substitution \(\sigma\) such that \(\sigma(x) = x\) for all \(x \in X\). On the other hand, \(Z\) is said to be defined explicitly in terms of \(X\) by means of \(\Gamma\) in \(\vdash\) when, for every \(z \in Z\), there exists a formula \(\varphi_{z}\) over \(X\) such that \[ \Gamma \vdash z \leftrightarrow \varphi_{z}. \] Then the infinite Beth property postulates the equivalence of implicit and explicit definability in \(\vdash\) (for all \(X,Z,\Gamma\) as above).